You are here:
AustLII >>
Databases >>
International Journal for Crime, Justice and Social Democracy >>
2019 >>
[2019] IntJlCrimJustSocDem 41
Database Search
| Name Search
| Recent Articles
| Noteup
| LawCite
| Author Info
| Download
| Help
Walklate, Sandra; Fitz-Gibbon, Kate --- "The Criminalisation of Coercive Control: the Power of Law?" [2019] IntJlCrimJustSocDem 41; (2019) 8(4) International Journal for Crime, Justice and Social Democracy 94
- Introduction
- Making sense of intimate partner violence (IPV) has long been seen through the lens of coercive control (Johnson 1995; Schechter 1982;
Stark 2007). Indeed, in a recent overview of research on this topic, Hamberger, Larsen and Lehrner (2017) identify 22 different ways
of defining and operationalising coercive control, all of which generate findings with different emphases. Nonetheless, their review
of this work points to three features of coercive control on which there seems to be some agreement: intentionality on the part of
the abuser; the negative perception of the controlling behaviour on the part of the victim; and the abuser’s ability to obtain
control by use of a credible threat. Taking these three features together, it is easy to see how Stark (2007: 13) understands coercive
control as a ‘liberty crime’ and an endemic feature of wider gender inequalities experienced by women across the globe
(see also Kelly and Westmarland 2016; Manjoo 2016; World Health Organization (WHO) 2013). The concept itself certainly encourages
a deeper appreciation of the hidden and intrusive consequences of ‘dimensions of partner abuse that have gone largely unnoticed
and that are not normally associated with assault’ (Stark 2007: 204) such as, for example, psychological abuse, intimidation
and isolation. Moreover, it is a concept designed to capture the long-term, ongoing nature of a wide range of forms of violence,
not exclusively physical, that can pervade women’s (and some men’s) routine daily lives. However, despite the longstanding
presence of this way of thinking about men’s violence, it is only in recent years that efforts have been made to recognise
coercive control within the legal context. The purpose of this article is to explore these efforts and to offer some reflections
on the extent to which the law per se has the power, or indeed the capacity, to respond to what is known about coercive control.
-
- This exploration occurs in four parts. The first offers a brief overview of the varied ways in which coercive control has entered
legal discourse in different jurisdictions. The second part maps these efforts onto evidence of the nature and extent of coercive
control in everyday life. In placing the legal and the everyday side by side, the third part of the article goes on to consider the
extent to which recourse to the law, understood as a feature of ‘coercive control creep’, carries with it unintended
consequences, particularly for those it is intended to help. The final and concluding part considers the extent to which, in light
of the preceding discussion, the law can be an efficacious route to responding to the everyday nature of IPV.
- Coercive control and criminal law
- When considered through Stark’s conceptualisation of a ‘liberty crime’, it is easy to see how coercive control has
become harnessed more recently in the domain of criminal justice. Nevertheless, as Williamson (2010) has pointed out, reframing domestic
violence in this way poses challenges for all those working within this field for two reasons. Firstly, it focuses attention on the
impact of a wider range of abusive behaviours (some criminalised, some not) on the victim. Secondly, for criminal justice professionals,
it moves the focus away from responding to victims in an individual incident-led approach to a process-led manner that is concerned
with addressing the cumulative effect of the minutiae of everyday behaviours. As Renzetti (1992) observed some time ago, finding
the balance between autonomy and intimacy is a challenge faced by all relationships; consequently, appreciating how and when that
challenge becomes coercive and controlling is both important and difficult. Nevertheless, reframing IPV as a liberty crime has created
the space for a range of different criminal law interventions. These potentialities range from the use of coercive control in expert
testimony in court proceedings to its use as a specific defence for action taken, particularly in cases of homicide, as a constituent
element of specific offences, and as a specific criminal offence in its own right. It will be useful to say a little about each of
these in turn, though it is the last of these interventions which has provoked the most reform activity and contemporary academic
interest.
-
-
- Coercive control in court: The use of expert testimony in criminal cases
- Sheehy (2018) offers a detailed analysis of efforts in the case of Teresa Craig in Canada to invoke coercive control as self-defence
in her trial for the murder of her partner. This is an interesting case in itself since Evan Stark was brought to the court as an
expert witness. While his status as an expert witness was subjected to some considerable debate by the court, he was permitted to
testify on Craig’s behalf. The court was clearly rather more familiar with psychiatrists and psychologists providing reports
in respect of post-traumatic stress disorder and battered women’s syndrome as part of the defence in cases of this kind; evidence
of coercive control was new ground. Sheehy (2018) documents the difficulties this strategy posed for the court and suggests that,
without the broader criminalisation of coercive control, it is a strategy unlikely to prove successful in Canada.
- In a comparative analysis of two cases and their associated judgements in New Zealand (NZ),1 Midson (2016) also considers the possibilities
of coercive control as a specific defence for murder. Using these two cases as illustrative, she explores the question of culpability
and responsibility and their relevance for such cases. She concludes by suggesting:
- The tension between culpability and responsibility in cases that lack physical evidence (e.g., of injury or the use of tracking devices
and so on) in support of a partial or complete defence to murder has recently been tested in England and Wales in the appeal case
of Sally Challen. In February 2019, Challen successfully appealed her 2011 conviction for the murder of her husband, with the Court
of Appeal quashing her original conviction for murder. In what has been described by Women’s Aid (2019) as a ‘bittersweet
victory’ for Challen, the court simultaneously ordered that Challen be retried for murder based on new evidence that she was
suffering from a mental disorder at the time of the killing. In her original trial, Challen’s defence team unsuccessfully raised
a partial defence of diminished responsibility. While coercive control has not been introduced as a specific (partial or complete)
defence to murder, it was introduced as a standalone criminal offence in England and Wales in 2015 (discussed more fully below),
four years after Challen’s conviction. Much of the media coverage in the lead-up to Challen’s appeal focused on the new
legislation and the possibility that it would be pivotal in contextualising Challen’s actions for the court. However, the appeal
judgement suggests that the evidence of coercive control was less pivotal than expected, with Lady Justice Hallett stating:
- As such, this case, as yet, does little to demonstrate how evidence of coercive control can be used at trial or on appeal to allow
the courts to understand better and respond to the circumstances within which women kill their prolonged domestic abusers. However,
understanding these circumstances has been valuable in challenging accepted interpretations of provocation as a partial defence for
murder, as illustrated in the work of Fitz-Gibbon (2014), and the Challen case (who was released in June 2019 after the Crown accepted
a guilty pleas to manslaughter) may further an appreciation of these kinds of circumstances.
- Coercive control as an adjunct to already criminalised behaviours
- While the use of expert testimony to enable a jury to appreciate the particular circumstances that may result in murder takes different
forms across different jurisdictions, in some countries consideration is being given to the role of coercive control as a specific
feature or as an adjunct to behaviours already criminalised. For example, Ortiz (2018) notes that Tennessee has followed the example
of the law now on the statute books in England and Wales and adapted its law on false imprisonment to include a specific category
of behaviours she defines as domestic false imprisonment. This, she argues, maintains compliance with the American Constitution on the need for legal clarity, while at the same time capturing the essence of coercive control. Thus, domestic false imprisonment
could be defined as:
-
- In a similar vein, Stansfield and Williams (2018) provide evidence for understanding non-fatal strangulation in coercive control.
In their United States (US) case data, they explore the relationship between the use of threats to kill and the delivery of such
threats. They conclude that:
- In highlighting this link, their work contributes to a global debate concerning the introduction of specific offences of strangulation.
Such offences exist in 47 jurisdictions in the US (Theakston 2019), have been introduced in NZ (s. 189A Family Violence (Amendments)
Act 2018; see further Law Commission 2016) and have been introduced and/or debated in a number of Australian states and territories
(Fitz-Gibbon et al. 2018; Gotsis 2018).
-
- The work of Stansfield and Williams (2018) is clearly suggestive of a need to at least reframe understandings of such existing laws
in light of coercive control. This legal strategy focuses considerable attention on the role of practitioners in embracing such understandings
(see also Brennan et al. 2018). However, some jurisdictions have taken the concept of coercive control further and have introduced
specific legislation designed to capture the wide range and ongoing nature of behaviours included within it.
-
- A specific offence of coercive control
- The introduction of new criminal law offences designed specifically to capture coercive and controlling behaviours is arguably where
the translation of the clinical notion of coercive control into the legal realm has animated most debate. Over the last 10 years,
new offences have been introduced to varying degrees across the United Kingdom, Europe and Australia (Douglas 2015) and debated in
the US (Tuerkheimer 2007). While these offences have taken varied forms—in terms of the label applied to the abusive behaviour
they are designed to address and in terms of their inclusivity (e.g., some are gender-specific and/or apply only to those in intimate
partner relationships)—at the core of each has been an argument that a new category of criminal offence is necessary to capture
a pattern of abusive behaviours the law is otherwise incapable of responding to. However, the operation of these new categories has
arguably raised more questions than answers in terms of the merits of, and need for, more law to improve justice system responses
to IPV.
- Exemplifying an earlier reform of this kind, in Australia, the Tasmanian Family Violence Act 2004 (Tas) introduced two new offences: one of economic abuse and one of emotional abuse and intimidation. Both fit within the rubric
of coercive control and indeed, both are couched in terms of an ongoing course of conduct. Yet, to date, neither has resulted in
many prosecutions. In a detailed examination of the operation of these offences, McMahon and McGorrery (2016) suggest several reasons
for this, drawing attention to the flaws inherent in their formulation rather than a failure of take-up on the part of legal practitioners.
In sum, their analysis suggests that these laws are limited by the fact that:
- • Incidents need to be reported within 12 months of their occurrence
- • The legislative drafting suffers from lack of clarity concerning understandings of reasonableness in relation to each of these
behaviours
- • There are difficulties in operationalising emotional abuse in the legal context
- • There are overlaps between the offences in terms of what is included/excluded
- • There are overlaps between these offences and other offences on the statute books, arguably making both redundant.
- This analysis of these specific offences in a small Australian jurisdiction echoes some of the commentaries in relation to the offence
of coercive and controlling behaviour introduced in England and Wales on December 2015, to which we now turn our attention.
- Section 76 of the Serious Crime Act (England and Wales) 2015 states:
- For the purposes of the English legislation, coercive control is defined as behaviour:
- While limited to persons who live together and/or who are in a current intimate relationship, this offence covers a wide range of
behaviours (Home Office 2015) and explicitly draws on the work of Stark (2007), with the key exception that the offence is defined
in gender-neutral terms. This is a significant departure from Stark’s (2007) conceptualisation of coercive control and stands
in contrast to the Scottish legislation introduced in 2018, which recognises the gendered pattern of domestic abuse and also includes
ex-partners within its remit (Domestic Abuse (Scotland) Act 2018; see further Burman and Brooks-Hay 2018; Stark and Hester 2019).
- In terms of take-up by the criminal justice system, there were just over 9,000 offences of coercive control recorded by the police
in England and Wales in the year ending March 2018, out of a total of just over 2 million incidents of domestic abuse recorded for
that year (Office of National Statistics 2018). These figures represent a doubling of coercive control offences recorded for 2017,
clearly indicative of this new legislation gaining a foothold among practitioners. However, as the data reported by McClenaghan and
Boutaud (2017) illustrate, the take-up has been patchy with varying levels of implementation by different police forces.
-
- Early evaluations of the English legislation point to problems for frontline police officers in ‘seeing’ coercive control
(Wiener 2017), in practitioner understandings of coercive control more generally (Brennan et al. 2018; Robinson, Myhill and Wire
2018) and problems associated with providing evidence of this offence (Bishop and Bettinson 2018). However, despite mixed evaluations
of its early operation, like offences have continued to emerge in nearby jurisdictions, including the aforementioned Scottish offence
and most recently, the introduction of a new offence of coercive control in Ireland, under section 39 of the Domestic Violence Act.
-
- Many of the problems highlighted above are not new to the field of domestic abuse; in many ways, despite its symbolic power, the law
itself is a blunt instrument in affording change to the wider social practices of violence rooted in gender inequality (see further
Fitz-Gibbon, McCulloch and Walklate 2017; Goodmark 2018). Tolmie (2018) offers a substantial summary of the arguments both for and
against using the law in this way, with Douglas (2018) adding the potential for criminal justice systems’ abuse to the list
of abuses women already experience in their relationship with the law. Walklate, Fitz-Gibbon and McCulloch (2018) offer a more detailed
analysis of the specific problems associated with this particular offence, while Burman and Brooks-Hay (2018: 78) conclude their
analysis of the prospective Scottish legislation by stating:
-
- Of course, here Burman and Brooks-Hay (2018) are articulating a longstanding dilemma within this field concerning the extent to which
recourse to the law can make a difference (see also Goodmark 2018). This recourse to the law fails to recognise the law itself as
coercive and controlling (Douglas 2018), the problems of operationalising coercion as it already exists within legal discourse (Brunk
1979) and the associated problems of (in)voluntariness (Kuennan 2014). All of these issues are returned to below; however, at this
juncture it is of value to note that the early evaluations of this specific legal intervention, alongside other strategies listed
above, more often than not replicate the problem of defining coercive control, as identified by Hamberger, Larsen and Lehrner (2017),
now reappearing in problems of policy implementation. Thus, taken together, these issues unveil the potential of (mis)recognition
of coercive control for perpetrators, victims and practitioners alike, perhaps leading to the fundamental question asked by Crossman
and Hardesty (2018: 196): ‘what makes control coercive?’ It is to this question that this article turns next.
- Coercive control in everyday life
- It is without a doubt that coercive control operates in a myriad of ways in women’s (and some men’s) everyday lives. Variously
envisaged as a cage (Stark 2007) or as a web, tree or trap (Pitman 2017), its effects can be experienced cognitively, emotionally
and socially, frequently resulting in its victims being isolated, with little sense of self-worth or self-esteem.
-
- Most often conceptualised in terms of the everyday effects of wider patriarchal social relationships, the presence of coercive control
and its value as a concept has been recently demonstrated through the use of digital media as a means of control (see, e.g., Douglas,
Harris and Dragiewicz 2019; Harris and Woodlock 2019), in directing practices of ‘good’ mothering (Heward-Belle 2017;
Radford and Hester 2006), use as a tool in making sense of ‘custody stalking’ (Elizabeth 2017) and is well recognised
as a non-violent mechanism of control (Crossman, Hardesty and Raffaelli 2016; Stark 2007).
-
- The presence of coercive control in intimate partner relationships specifically in terms of physical coercion and control has been
shown to impact children2 (Callaghan et al. 2018; McLeod 2018) and is no respecter of age, ethnicity, ability or culture. However,
despite its pervasive nature, the questions of intent on the part of the perpetrator and the negative perception and the credibility
of the associated threats on the part of the victim remain central to any potential impact this range of abusive behaviours might
have. So, when does control become coercive, or as Kuennan (2014) might say, when is enough, enough?
-
- In a recent empirical excavation of this question, Crossman and Hardesty (2018) draw the distinction between women’s experiences
of constraint through commitment and constraint through force. Their (retrospective) data from interviews with 22 divorced women
identified control as a feature of all these women’s relationships. However, such control manifested itself in two different
ways. For some women in their sample, control/constraint was felt and experienced as part of the compromises made through their commitment
to the relationship, which might have also involved making sacrifices in the interests of their marriage or children. Many of these
experiences could be seen to be associated with the kind of social norms and expectations permeating their lives.
-
- In contrast, for those women who experienced constraint through force, the emphasis was different, even though the compromises and
behaviours may have been the same. For these women, the men in their lives used social norms and expectations to constrain them.
Interestingly, the use of physical violence against them featured for women in both these groups, but the variations in control they
experienced were not contingent upon the violence itself. These findings, Crossman and Hardesty (2015) suggest, support the notion
of entrapment being used by some men to control their partners and lend support to the view that it is not the behaviours per se
that are problematic, but the frequency with which they are used. This work centres the importance of women’s understandings
of the nature and extent of the manipulation and exploitation they are experiencing.
- Crossman and Hardesty’s study clearly lends support to the presence of coercive control in relationships but adds a more nuanced
understanding of its manifestation in recognising how control might be experienced as either a positive commitment to working in
a relationship or as entrapment. Recognising the difference between these circumstances then becomes a critical issue for practitioners
and legal responses.
- Importantly, these findings, which resonate with the tension between autonomy and intimacy raised by Renzetti (1992) some time ago,
imply that control is not always coercive. Moreover, when applied in the context of criminal justice responses, they also pose the
inherently tricky question: when does a ‘normal’ intimate partner relationship become criminal? (On the blurriness between
coercive control, romance and intimate partner relationships, see e.g., Chung 2005). So while coercive control has been, and is,
an enlightening descriptive tool for a range of behaviours, how—and under what conditions—an appreciation of relationship
processes can inform criminal justice intervention remains a moot point. The difficulty with identifying coercive and controlling
behaviours as criminal is well captured by Bishop (2016: 2), who explains:
- In some ways, these observations allude to the well-recognised tension between the ‘isolated’ incident-led focus of criminal
justice responses to date, and the process of responding to a series of interrelated experiences that the concept of coercive control
endeavours to convey. This tension is not easy to address since the recognition of process belies further underlying difficulties
with what might be called ‘coercive control creep’.
- Coercive control creep and its unintended consequences
- Efforts to respond to violence against women have fuelled criminal justice policy agendas across the globe since the mid-1980s. The
dominance of North American voices in shaping these policy agendas has been well documented by Goodmark (2015). Similarly, the efficacy
of these same policies has come under increasing scrutiny, with researchers noting that the mere introduction and ‘travelling’
nature of such policies should not be misinterpreted as evidence of their effectiveness in practice (Goodmark 2015; Walklate and
Fitz-Gibbon 2018).
- In some ways, coercive control creep, the increasingly present use of this concept as a point of uncontested reference, emulates this
policy process. Throughout this process, little thought has apparently been given to alternatives to criminalisation; Goodmark (2017)
outlines some of the possible reasons for this. At the same time, there is sufficient evidence pointing to the unintended consequences
of harnessing the law in this way—particularly for those whom it is believed might be protected by the law (see, e.g., Douglas
2018; Tolmie 2018)—with protection from the law being additionally problematic for Indigenous women (Blagg 2016), women with
disabilities (Thiara, Hague and Mullender 2011) and those from ethnic minorities (Gill and Harrison 2017). This evidence is multifaceted
and multilayered, ranging from the specific consequences associated with particular legal strategies to the more general question
of what response women (in violent relationships) might want from a criminal justice system and what they might receive in reality.
The criminalisation of coercive control has drawn comment along all these dimensions.
-
- The creation of any new offence in this field places women squarely within the domain of criminal justice. Yet, the difficulties faced
by women in dealing with criminal justice systems are both well-known and profound. As Hanna (2009) has commented, the more the criminal
law tries to intervene on behalf of women, the more challenges it poses for them. From the point of contact with a frontline police
officer, to presenting evidence at court, to dispositions by the court—whether criminal or civil—all present a range
of hurdles for women to negotiate. The nature of these experiences can be contingent on a wide range of variables, including class,
ethnicity and cultural background.
-
- However, a major contributing factor is fear: fear of their partner, fear of the system and fear of what they might lose by exposing
themselves to the criminal justice process (e.g., their role as mothers to their children). These concerns have persisted, decades
of policy activity notwithstanding. Responding to these concerns is not solely about training (criminal justice) professionals to
respond more appropriately to women living with violence, though without a doubt, more could be done in this respect.
- In particular, the creation of a new offence does not deal with any of the well-documented concerns women have for not engaging with
the criminal justice process and, as Douglas (2018) has observed, may also create new opportunities for what she has termed ‘legal
systems abuse’: perpetrators using the legal system to further assert control over their partners (see, e.g., research on protection
orders and the criminalisation of women victims: Douglas and Fitzgerald 2018; Douglas and Nancarrow 2014). Additionally, such abuse
can also contribute to the criminalisation of women, adding to their concerns about engagement with legal processes at all (see further
Tolmie 2018).
-
- The concerns consistently expressed by women also touch upon questions of what it is they would want from any intervention, legal
or otherwise (as opposed to what activists might want or what policymakers and practitioners might be charged with delivering). Classic
understandings of women living with violence point to evidence that, if it is the woman herself who has asked for help or support,
more often than not she just wants the behaviour of her partner, both violent and non-violent in all of its intimidating and fear-inducing
manifestations, to stop (see, inter alia, Kirkwood 1993). Sometimes, for some women, love still matters (Kuennen 2014). So, wanting
undesirable behaviour to stop does not necessarily equate with wanting a partner’s behaviour to be subjected to criminal sanction.
-
- Clearly, for some behaviours, particularly those of physical violence, a woman’s wishes in this respect can quite legitimately,
in terms of the law, be ignored. Even in cases where women do seek legal intervention and a punitive criminal justice system outcome,
the criminalisation of coercive control in and of itself does little to address the long-held barriers women victims of IPV have
faced in accessing justice (on this, see further Walklate, Fitz-Gibbon and McCulloch 2018). To this end, introducing coercive control
as a standalone offence presumes that women will have access to police, that police will have access to the required evidence, and
the legal frameworks of the inherently masculine criminal court system will be open to their experiences of a pattern of abuse. When
considered from that vantage, it is a lot to expect from a single piece of legislative law reform.
-
- Consequently, when women’s everyday experiences of control in their relationships (not all of which will be seen by them as
coercive) are put alongside what they might want from any intervention, there is no necessary neatness of fit. Indeed, neither is
there a neatness of fit with the policy responses claiming to meet their interests. Two issues arise as a consequence of this. The
first is concerned with the relationship between individual autonomy and agency and the ongoing concern to criminalise coercive control.
The second is concerned with how coercive control in and of itself can downplay violence in relationships, which arguably, is the
very issue that is better dealt with through a legal response. Each of these will be discussed in turn.
-
- Kuennen (2014) discusses coercive control and the efforts to embrace this concept in criminal justice as the legal erasure of agency.
This observation is similar to that made by Brunk (1979) some time ago in his discussion of the legal dilemma posed by the concept
of coercion per se and what this implies for individual choice—or, as Kuennen (2014) might say—agency. Perhaps, to put
it more squarely in the discussion here, the question arises as to what this legal erasure implies for women who choose to live with
constraint, whether that be through commitment (Crossman and Hardesty 2018) or as a result of any other motivation. There is here
a further question concerning what a normal relationship might look like and who decides on such normality.
-
- The criminal law proves a blunt instrument for drawing such distinctions; as Hanna (2009: 1468) has argued, it ‘forces the question
of coercion into a yes or no answer. The line between free choice and coercion gets drawn somewhere—and you are either coercive
or not’ (see also Walklate, Fitz-Gibbon and McCulloch 2018). Problematically, when these distinctions are drawn in the realm
of law, it is not the individual experiencing the behaviour who decides whether the actions constitute coercive control or which
actions should be considered criminal, but rather the legal actors involved. The erasure of agency in this way carries implications,
of course, not just for women in cases of coercive control, but for all women, particularly as legal discourses can be, and are,
used for purposes other than they were intended (Smart 1989). The potential slippage from individual women to all women highlights
the slipperiness of coercive control as a concept (Hamberger, Larsen and Lehrner 2017), and as a result, its lack of specificity—particularly
in the law—carries with it significant unintended consequences for its use.
-
- Ultimately, of course, the law itself must also be recognised as a site of coercion, alongside a range of other sources of sanction
that coerce individuals to do things because they are afraid or intimidated to do otherwise. Brauer, Tittle and Antonaccio (2017)
make the distinction between erratic and oppressive coercion in endeavouring to understand coercion as a feature of all aspects of
offending behaviour and its consequences. However, for the purposes of this discussion, it is sufficient to note that the proponents
of coercive control view its presence in women’s lives as though it was separate and separable from their experiences of coercion
in other aspects of their lives and/or separate from the human condition experienced by everyone.
-
- The second issue to be addressed here, the erasure of physical violence, has been discussed at length by Walby and Towers (2018).
Their concern with downplaying physical violence and its importance in intimate partner relationships is as much methodological as
it is conceptual, although these two concerns are connected. The absence of conceptual clarity impedes measurement efforts, and for
Walby and Towers (2018), any agenda focused on violence against women demands accurate measures, since it is these measurements and
the counting of violence that ultimately persuade governments to take action across a wide range of domains, including but not limited
to the legal domain.
-
- However, police preoccupation with the presence of physical violence, for example, as a means of informing their decision-making in
relation to violence against women is well documented (see, e.g., Robinson, Pinchevsky and Guthrie, 2018). Physical violence can
more often than not be evidenced and can result in the kind of criminalisation that is pursued by those wanting to criminalise coercive
control. Thus, there is a conundrum here in the way in which coercive control as a concept downplays the physically violent aspect
of women’s lives that can be responded to more or less adequately by the incident-led response of the law, while it simultaneously
places demands on criminal justice systems that, as yet, have been shown to be less well equipped to respond to when compared with
response to physical violence.
-
- In this respect, a concern emerges that begs the question of whether, in seeking to criminalise a wider range of abusive behaviours,
the day-to-day operation of an offence of coercive control may also serve to hide acts of physical violence. Such hiding has far-reaching
implications in terms of assessments of perpetrator risk, management of victim safety and seriousness of criminal justice system
intervention.
- Conclusion: Coercive control, meaning and consequences
- A number of themes run through this paper, some of which contribute to a bigger question and debate recently posed by Goodmark (2018)
on decriminalising domestic violence. The coercive control creep documented here stands as testimony to some aspects of that more
significant question. In particular, the criminalisation of coercive control may fail women in two respects. Firstly, it arguably
fails at the conceptual level, in misunderstanding the coercive nature of the law and the inability to appreciate how this concept
contributes to the process of erasing women’s agency. Secondly, it fails at the experiential level, in failing to see women’s
lives as a whole, particularly their reluctances to engage with criminal justice. Put simply, coercive control fails to ‘see’
responses to violence against women holistically and, in so doing, leaves the subject of law untouched (Naffine 2003).
- Some time ago, Naffine (1990) observed that the subject of law was the rational, middle-class entrepreneurial male. Law was made and
practised with this subject in mind. This subject renders all those who fall outside of its parameters ‘other’, in both
their experiences of the law and the likelihood that the law can ‘see’ or ‘hear’ them (Easteal, Bartels and
Mittal 2019; Hudson 2006). In her later essay, Naffine (2003) sees little to be optimistic about the hold this subject of law has
on law’s formulation and practice. However, following Smart (1989) and more recently, Howe and Alaattinoğlu (2019), this
does not necessarily mean that law is not a site for action. It is. However, the law itself will never be enough, and this truism
has abounded in this field since the advent of second-wave feminism (see, e.g., Wilson 1983). Coercive control is a constituent element
in framing our understandings of the pervasive impact of a wide range of behaviours on women’s lives, but the law and its inherent
power structure is a very blunt instrument to address the concerns it brings to the fore. In this respect, more law is definitely
not the answer and only furthers the exclusion of those already excluded from criminal justice.
-
- Correspondence:
- Sandra Walklate, Eleanor Rathbone Chair of Sociology at the University of Liverpool (Liverpool, United Kingdom) conjoint Chair of
Criminology, Monash University (Victoria, Australia). Email: S.L.Walklate@liverpool.ac.uk
- Dr Kate Fitz-Gibbon, School of Social Sciences, Faculty of Arts, Monash University. 20 Chancellor's Walk, Clayton VIC 3800, Australia.
Email: kate.fitzgibbon@monash.edu
-
- References
-
The Criminalisation of Coercive Control: The Power of Law?
Sandra Walklate
University of Liverpool, United Kingdom
Monash University, Australia
Kate Fitz-Gibbon
Monash University, Australia
Abstract
Making sense of intimate partner violence has long been seen through the
lens of coercive control. However, despite the longstanding
presence of this
concept, it is only in recent years that efforts have been made to recognise
coercive control within the legal context.
This article examines the extent to
which the law per se has the power, or indeed the capacity, to respond to what
is known about
coercive control. To do so, it charts the varied ways in which
coercive control has entered legal discourse in different jurisdictions
and maps
these efforts onto what is evidenced about the nature and extent of coercive
control in everyday life. This article then
places the legal and the everyday
side by side and considers the unintended consequences of ‘coercive
control creep’.
In conclusion, it is suggested that the criminalisation of
coercive control only serves to fail those it is intended to protect.
Coercive control; intimate partner violence; criminal law; legal
discourse.
|
Please cite this article as:
Walklate S and Fitz-Gibbon K (2019) The criminalisation of coercive
control: The power of law? International Journal for Crime, Justice and
Social Democracy 8(4): 94-108. https://doi.org/10.5204/ijcjsd.v8i4.1205
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution
4.0 International Licence. As an open access journal, articles are free to
use with proper attribution. ISSN: 2202-8005
Introduction
Making
sense of intimate partner violence (IPV) has long been seen through the lens of
coercive control (Johnson 1995; Schechter 1982;
Stark 2007). Indeed, in a recent
overview of research on this topic, Hamberger, Larsen and Lehrner (2017)
identify 22 different ways
of defining and operationalising coercive control,
all of which generate findings with different emphases. Nonetheless, their
review
of this work points to three features of coercive control on which there
seems to be some agreement: intentionality on the part of
the abuser; the
negative perception of the controlling behaviour on the part of the victim; and
the abuser’s ability to obtain
control by use of a credible threat. Taking
these three features together, it is easy to see how Stark (2007: 13)
understands coercive
control as a ‘liberty crime’ and an endemic
feature of wider gender inequalities experienced by women across the globe
(see
also Kelly and Westmarland 2016; Manjoo 2016; World Health Organization (WHO)
2013). The concept itself certainly encourages
a deeper appreciation of the
hidden and intrusive consequences of ‘dimensions of partner abuse that
have gone largely unnoticed
and that are not normally associated with
assault’ (Stark 2007: 204) such as, for example, psychological abuse,
intimidation
and isolation. Moreover, it is a concept designed to capture the
long-term, ongoing nature of a wide range of forms of violence,
not exclusively
physical, that can pervade women’s (and some men’s) routine daily
lives. However, despite the longstanding
presence of this way of thinking about
men’s violence, it is only in recent years that efforts have been made to
recognise
coercive control within the legal context. The purpose of this article
is to explore these efforts and to offer some reflections
on the extent to which
the law per se has the power, or indeed the capacity, to respond to what is
known about coercive
control.
This exploration
occurs in four parts. The first offers a brief overview of the varied ways in
which coercive control has entered
legal discourse in different jurisdictions.
The second part maps these efforts onto evidence of the nature and extent of
coercive
control in everyday life. In placing the legal and the everyday side by
side, the third part of the article goes on to consider the
extent to which
recourse to the law, understood as a feature of ‘coercive control
creep’, carries with it unintended
consequences, particularly for those it
is intended to help. The final and concluding part considers the extent to
which, in light
of the preceding discussion, the law can be an efficacious route
to responding to the everyday nature of IPV.
Coercive control and criminal law
When considered through Stark’s conceptualisation
of a ‘liberty crime’, it is easy to see how coercive control has
become harnessed more recently in the domain of criminal justice. Nevertheless,
as Williamson (2010) has pointed out, reframing domestic
violence in this way
poses challenges for all those working within this field for two reasons.
Firstly, it focuses attention on the
impact of a wider range of abusive
behaviours (some criminalised, some not) on the victim. Secondly, for criminal
justice professionals,
it moves the focus away from responding to victims in an
individual incident-led approach to a process-led manner that is concerned
with
addressing the cumulative effect of the minutiae of everyday behaviours. As
Renzetti (1992) observed some time ago, finding
the balance between autonomy and
intimacy is a challenge faced by all relationships; consequently, appreciating
how and when that
challenge becomes coercive and controlling is both important
and difficult. Nevertheless, reframing IPV as a liberty crime has created
the
space for a range of different criminal law interventions. These potentialities
range from the use of coercive control in expert
testimony in court proceedings
to its use as a specific defence for action taken, particularly in cases of
homicide, as a constituent
element of specific offences, and as a specific
criminal offence in its own right. It will be useful to say a little about each
of
these in turn, though it is the last of these interventions which has
provoked the most reform activity and contemporary academic
interest.
Coercive
control in court: The use of expert testimony in criminal
cases
Sheehy (2018) offers a detailed
analysis of efforts in the case of Teresa Craig in Canada to invoke coercive
control as self-defence
in her trial for the murder of her partner. This is an
interesting case in itself since Evan Stark was brought to the court as an
expert witness. While his status as an expert witness was subjected to some
considerable debate by the court, he was permitted to
testify on Craig’s
behalf. The court was clearly rather more familiar with psychiatrists and
psychologists providing reports
in respect of post-traumatic stress disorder and
battered women’s syndrome as part of the defence in cases of this kind;
evidence
of coercive control was new ground. Sheehy (2018) documents the
difficulties this strategy posed for the court and suggests that,
without the
broader criminalisation of coercive control, it is a strategy unlikely to prove
successful in Canada.
In a comparative analysis of two cases and their
associated judgements in New Zealand
(NZ),[1] Midson (2016) also considers
the possibilities of coercive control as a specific defence for murder. Using
these two cases as illustrative,
she explores the question of culpability and
responsibility and their relevance for such cases. She concludes by
suggesting:
When victims of coercive control kill their abusers there is no ‘malice
aforethought’ in the true sense of that phrase,
despite the appearance of
willed action. The act is not malicious or angry—it is a normative
response to coercive conditions.
On that basis, it is not just or fair to label
these victims as ‘murderers’ or ‘killers’, even though
the
criminal justice system might rightly hold them responsible to some degree.
(Midson 2016: 1272)
The tension between culpability and responsibility in
cases that lack physical evidence (e.g., of injury or the use of tracking
devices
and so on) in support of a partial or complete defence to murder has
recently been tested in England and Wales in the appeal case
of Sally Challen.
In February 2019, Challen successfully appealed her 2011 conviction for the
murder of her husband, with the Court
of Appeal quashing her original conviction
for murder. In what has been described by Women’s Aid (2019) as a
‘bittersweet
victory’ for Challen, the court simultaneously ordered
that Challen be retried for murder based on new evidence that she was
suffering
from a mental disorder at the time of the killing. In her original trial,
Challen’s defence team unsuccessfully raised
a partial defence of
diminished responsibility. While coercive control has not been introduced as a
specific (partial or complete)
defence to murder, it was introduced as a
standalone criminal offence in England and Wales in 2015 (discussed more fully
below),
four years after Challen’s conviction. Much of the media coverage
in the lead-up to Challen’s appeal focused on the new
legislation and the
possibility that it would be pivotal in contextualising Challen’s actions
for the court. However, the appeal
judgement suggests that the evidence of
coercive control was less pivotal than expected, with Lady Justice Hallett
stating:
There might be those out there who think this appeal is all about coercive
control but it’s not ... Primarily, it’s about
diagnosis of
disorders that were undiagnosed at the time of the trial. (cited in Curtis 2019:
7)
As such, this case, as yet, does little to demonstrate
how evidence of coercive control can be used at trial or on appeal to allow
the
courts to understand better and respond to the circumstances within which women
kill their prolonged domestic abusers. However,
understanding these
circumstances has been valuable in challenging accepted interpretations of
provocation as a partial defence for
murder, as illustrated in the work of
Fitz-Gibbon (2014), and the Challen case (who was released in June 2019 after
the Crown accepted
a guilty pleas to manslaughter) may further an appreciation
of these kinds of circumstances.
Coercive control as an adjunct to already
criminalised behaviours
While the use of
expert testimony to enable a jury to appreciate the particular circumstances
that may result in murder takes different
forms across different jurisdictions,
in some countries consideration is being given to the role of coercive control
as a specific
feature or as an adjunct to behaviours already criminalised. For
example, Ortiz (2018) notes that Tennessee has followed the example
of the law
now on the statute books in England and Wales and adapted its law on false
imprisonment to include a specific category
of behaviours she defines as
domestic false imprisonment. This, she argues, maintains compliance with the
American Constitution on
the need for legal clarity, while at the same time
capturing the essence of coercive control. Thus, domestic false imprisonment
could
be defined as:
A course of conduct intentional, knowing, reckless, or negligent repeated or
continuing harassment, intimidation, exploitation, humiliation,
isolation,
and/or control, directed toward a person with whom the perpetrator has a
personal connection, which interferes substantially
with that person's liberty
and autonomy. (Ortiz 2018: 707–708)
In a similar vein,
Stansfield and Williams (2018) provide evidence for understanding non-fatal
strangulation in coercive control.
In their United States (US) case data, they
explore the relationship between the use of threats to kill and the delivery of
such
threats. They conclude that:
The results consistently showed a robust empirical relation between
perpetrators’ death threats and subsequent escalation into
nonfatal
strangulation as a way of maintaining control through fear and intimidation.
(Stansfield and Williams 2018: 14)
In highlighting this link, their work contributes to a
global debate concerning the introduction of specific offences of strangulation.
Such offences exist in 47 jurisdictions in the US (Theakston 2019), have been
introduced in NZ (s. 189A Family Violence (Amendments) Act 2018; see
further Law Commission 2016) and have been introduced and/or debated in a number
of Australian states and territories (Fitz-Gibbon
et al. 2018; Gotsis
2018).
The work of Stansfield
and Williams (2018) is clearly suggestive of a need to at least reframe
understandings of such existing laws
in light of coercive control. This legal
strategy focuses considerable attention on the role of practitioners in
embracing such understandings
(see also Brennan et al. 2018). However, some
jurisdictions have taken the concept of coercive control further and have
introduced
specific legislation designed to capture the wide range and ongoing
nature of behaviours included within
it.
A specific offence
of coercive control
The introduction of new
criminal law offences designed specifically to capture coercive and controlling
behaviours is arguably where
the translation of the clinical notion of coercive
control into the legal realm has animated most debate. Over the last 10 years,
new offences have been introduced to varying degrees across the United Kingdom,
Europe and Australia (Douglas 2015) and debated in
the US (Tuerkheimer 2007).
While these offences have taken varied forms—in terms of the label applied
to the abusive behaviour
they are designed to address and in terms of their
inclusivity (e.g., some are gender-specific and/or apply only to those in
intimate
partner relationships)—at the core of each has been an argument
that a new category of criminal offence is necessary to capture
a pattern of
abusive behaviours the law is otherwise incapable of responding to. However, the
operation of these new categories has
arguably raised more questions than
answers in terms of the merits of, and need for, more law to improve justice
system responses
to IPV.
Exemplifying an earlier
reform of this kind, in Australia, the Tasmanian Family Violence Act
2004 (Tas) introduced two new offences: one of economic abuse and one of
emotional abuse and intimidation. Both fit within the rubric
of coercive control
and indeed, both are couched in terms of an ongoing course of conduct. Yet, to
date, neither has resulted in
many prosecutions. In a detailed examination of
the operation of these offences, McMahon and McGorrery (2016) suggest several
reasons
for this, drawing attention to the flaws inherent in their formulation
rather than a failure of take-up on the part of legal practitioners.
In sum,
their analysis suggests that these laws are limited by the fact that:
• Incidents need to be reported within 12 months
of their occurrence
• The legislative drafting
suffers from lack of clarity concerning understandings of reasonableness in
relation to each of these
behaviours
• There
are difficulties in operationalising emotional abuse in the legal
context
• There are overlaps between the
offences in terms of what is
included/excluded
• There are overlaps between
these offences and other offences on the statute books, arguably making both
redundant.
This analysis of these specific offences in a small
Australian jurisdiction echoes some of the commentaries in relation to the
offence
of coercive and controlling behaviour introduced in England and Wales on
December 2015, to which we now turn our
attention.
Section 76 of the Serious Crime Act
(England and Wales) 2015 states:
A person (A) commits an offence [of coercive control] if—
(a) A repeatedly or continuously engages in behaviour towards another person (B)
that is controlling or coercive,
(b) At the time of the behaviour, A and B are personally connected,
(c) The behaviour has a serious effect on B, and
(d) A knows or ought to know that the behaviour will have a serious effect on
B.
For the purposes of the English legislation, coercive
control is defined as behaviour:
Which takes place ‘repeatedly or continuously’. The victim and
alleged perpetrator must be ‘personally connected’
at the time the
behaviour takes place. The behaviour must have had a ‘serious
effect’ on the victim, meaning that it
has caused the victim to fear
violence will be used against them on ‘at least two occasions’, or
it has had a ‘substantial
adverse effect on the victims’ day to day
activities’. The alleged perpetrator must have known that their behaviour
would
have a serious effect on the victim, or the behaviour must have been such
that he or she ‘ought to have known’ it would
have that effect.
(Home Office 2015: 2)
While limited to persons who live together and/or who
are in a current intimate relationship, this offence covers a wide range of
behaviours (Home Office 2015) and explicitly draws on the work of Stark (2007),
with the key exception that the offence is defined
in gender-neutral terms. This
is a significant departure from Stark’s (2007) conceptualisation of
coercive control and stands
in contrast to the Scottish legislation introduced
in 2018, which recognises the gendered pattern of domestic abuse and also
includes
ex-partners within its remit (Domestic Abuse (Scotland) Act
2018; see further Burman and Brooks-Hay 2018; Stark and Hester 2019).
In terms of take-up by the criminal justice system,
there were just over 9,000 offences of coercive control recorded by the police
in England and Wales in the year ending March 2018, out of a total of just over
2 million incidents of domestic abuse recorded for
that year (Office of National
Statistics 2018). These figures represent a doubling of coercive control
offences recorded for 2017,
clearly indicative of this new legislation gaining a
foothold among practitioners. However, as the data reported by McClenaghan and
Boutaud (2017) illustrate, the take-up has been patchy with varying levels of
implementation by different police
forces.
Early evaluations
of the English legislation point to problems for frontline police officers in
‘seeing’ coercive control
(Wiener 2017), in practitioner
understandings of coercive control more generally (Brennan et al. 2018;
Robinson, Myhill and Wire
2018) and problems associated with providing evidence
of this offence (Bishop and Bettinson 2018). However, despite mixed evaluations
of its early operation, like offences have continued to emerge in nearby
jurisdictions, including the aforementioned Scottish offence
and most recently,
the introduction of a new offence of coercive control in Ireland, under section
39 of the Domestic Violence
Act.
Many of the
problems highlighted above are not new to the field of domestic abuse; in many
ways, despite its symbolic power, the law
itself is a blunt instrument in
affording change to the wider social practices of violence rooted in gender
inequality (see further
Fitz-Gibbon, McCulloch and Walklate 2017; Goodmark
2018). Tolmie (2018) offers a substantial summary of the arguments both for and
against using the law in this way, with Douglas (2018) adding the potential for
criminal justice systems’ abuse to the list
of abuses women already
experience in their relationship with the law. Walklate, Fitz-Gibbon and
McCulloch (2018) offer a more detailed
analysis of the specific problems
associated with this particular offence, while Burman and Brooks-Hay (2018: 78)
conclude their
analysis of the prospective Scottish legislation by stating:
Decades of policy and legislative reform of the criminal justice response to
other forms of violence against women leave us somewhat
pessimistic that the
introduction of this new offence within Scotland’s adversarial context,
which sustains forms of legal
practice known to effectively undermine the spirit
of any well-intentioned legislation, will fully achieve its bold ambitions ...
Legislative change cannot on its own lead to improvements. Whatever laws we have
will be only as effective as those who enforce,
prosecute and apply them.
Improving these practices – through education, training and embedding best
practice and domestic
abuse expertise – is likely to be more effective
than the creation of new offences alone.
Of course, here Burman and
Brooks-Hay (2018) are articulating a longstanding dilemma within this field
concerning the extent to which
recourse to the law can make a difference (see
also Goodmark 2018). This recourse to the law fails to recognise the law itself
as
coercive and controlling (Douglas 2018), the problems of operationalising
coercion as it already exists within legal discourse (Brunk
1979) and the
associated problems of (in)voluntariness (Kuennan 2014). All of these issues are
returned to below; however, at this
juncture it is of value to note that the
early evaluations of this specific legal intervention, alongside other
strategies listed
above, more often than not replicate the problem of defining
coercive control, as identified by Hamberger, Larsen and Lehrner (2017),
now
reappearing in problems of policy implementation. Thus, taken together, these
issues unveil the potential of (mis)recognition
of coercive control for
perpetrators, victims and practitioners alike, perhaps leading to the
fundamental question asked by Crossman
and Hardesty (2018: 196): ‘what
makes control coercive?’ It is to this question that this article turns
next.
Coercive control in everyday life
It is without a doubt that coercive control operates in
a myriad of ways in women’s (and some men’s) everyday lives.
Variously
envisaged as a cage (Stark 2007) or as a web, tree or trap (Pitman
2017), its effects can be experienced cognitively, emotionally
and socially,
frequently resulting in its victims being isolated, with little sense of
self-worth or
self-esteem.
Most often
conceptualised in terms of the everyday effects of wider patriarchal social
relationships, the presence of coercive control
and its value as a concept has
been recently demonstrated through the use of digital media as a means of
control (see, e.g., Douglas,
Harris and Dragiewicz 2019; Harris and Woodlock
2019), in directing practices of ‘good’ mothering (Heward-Belle
2017;
Radford and Hester 2006), use as a tool in making sense of ‘custody
stalking’ (Elizabeth 2017) and is well recognised
as a non-violent
mechanism of control (Crossman, Hardesty and Raffaelli 2016; Stark
2007).
The presence of
coercive control in intimate partner relationships specifically in terms of
physical coercion and control has been
shown to impact
children[2] (Callaghan et al. 2018;
McLeod 2018) and is no respecter of age, ethnicity, ability or culture. However,
despite its pervasive nature,
the questions of intent on the part of the
perpetrator and the negative perception and the credibility of the associated
threats
on the part of the victim remain central to any potential impact this
range of abusive behaviours might have. So, when does control
become coercive,
or as Kuennan (2014) might say, when is enough,
enough?
In a recent
empirical excavation of this question, Crossman and Hardesty (2018) draw the
distinction between women’s experiences
of constraint through commitment
and constraint through force. Their (retrospective) data from interviews with 22
divorced women
identified control as a feature of all these women’s
relationships. However, such control manifested itself in two different
ways.
For some women in their sample, control/constraint was felt and experienced as
part of the compromises made through their commitment
to the relationship, which
might have also involved making sacrifices in the interests of their marriage or
children. Many of these
experiences could be seen to be associated with the kind
of social norms and expectations permeating their
lives.
In contrast, for
those women who experienced constraint through force, the emphasis was
different, even though the compromises and
behaviours may have been the same.
For these women, the men in their lives used social norms and
expectations to constrain them. Interestingly, the use of physical violence
against them featured for women in both
these groups, but the variations in
control they experienced were not contingent upon the violence itself. These
findings, Crossman
and Hardesty (2015) suggest, support the notion of entrapment
being used by some men to control their partners and lend support to
the view
that it is not the behaviours per se that are problematic, but the frequency
with which they are used. This work centres
the importance of women’s
understandings of the nature and extent of the manipulation and exploitation
they are experiencing.
Crossman and Hardesty’s study clearly lends
support to the presence of coercive control in relationships but adds a more
nuanced
understanding of its manifestation in recognising how control might be
experienced as either a positive commitment to working in
a relationship or as
entrapment. Recognising the difference between these circumstances then becomes
a critical issue for practitioners
and legal responses.
Importantly, these findings, which resonate with the
tension between autonomy and intimacy raised by Renzetti (1992) some time ago,
imply that control is not always coercive. Moreover, when applied in the context
of criminal justice responses, they also pose the
inherently tricky question:
when does a ‘normal’ intimate partner relationship become criminal?
(On the blurriness between
coercive control, romance and intimate partner
relationships, see e.g., Chung 2005). So while coercive control has been, and
is,
an enlightening descriptive tool for a range of behaviours, how—and
under what conditions—an appreciation of relationship
processes can inform
criminal justice intervention remains a moot point. The difficulty with
identifying coercive and controlling
behaviours as criminal is well captured by
Bishop (2016: 2), who explains:
It’s difficult to objectively assess whether coercive control has taken
place. The abuser will typically use signals and covert
messages to exert and
maintain control and often these have meaning only in the context of that
particular relationship. For example,
the perpetrator may use a specific look,
phrase or movement to convey to the victim that they are close to breaking an
unspoken ‘rule’.
But these signals may be hard to classify as
abusive in and of themselves. Compliance with demands about dressing, shopping
or cooking
in a particular way to avoid repercussions may seem voluntary to an
outsider with little or no understanding of the dynamics in the
relationship.
In some ways, these observations allude to the
well-recognised tension between the ‘isolated’ incident-led focus of
criminal
justice responses to date, and the process of responding to a series of
interrelated experiences that the concept of coercive control
endeavours to
convey. This tension is not easy to address since the recognition of process
belies further underlying difficulties
with what might be called ‘coercive
control creep’.
Coercive control creep and its unintended
consequences
Efforts to respond to violence against women have
fuelled criminal justice policy agendas across the globe since the mid-1980s.
The
dominance of North American voices in shaping these policy agendas has been
well documented by Goodmark (2015). Similarly, the efficacy
of these same
policies has come under increasing scrutiny, with researchers noting that the
mere introduction and ‘travelling’
nature of such policies should
not be misinterpreted as evidence of their effectiveness in practice (Goodmark
2015; Walklate and
Fitz-Gibbon 2018).
In some ways, coercive control creep, the increasingly
present use of this concept as a point of uncontested reference, emulates this
policy process. Throughout this process, little thought has apparently been
given to alternatives to criminalisation; Goodmark (2017)
outlines some of the
possible reasons for this. At the same time, there is sufficient evidence
pointing to the unintended consequences
of harnessing the law in this
way—particularly for those whom it is believed might be protected by the
law (see, e.g., Douglas
2018; Tolmie 2018)—with protection from the law
being additionally problematic for Indigenous women (Blagg 2016), women with
disabilities (Thiara, Hague and Mullender 2011) and those from ethnic minorities
(Gill and Harrison 2017). This evidence is multifaceted
and multilayered,
ranging from the specific consequences associated with particular legal
strategies to the more general question
of what response women (in violent
relationships) might want from a criminal justice system and what they might
receive in reality.
The criminalisation of coercive control has drawn comment
along all these
dimensions.
The creation of
any new offence in this field places women squarely within the domain of
criminal justice. Yet, the difficulties faced
by women in dealing with criminal
justice systems are both well-known and profound. As Hanna (2009) has commented,
the more the criminal
law tries to intervene on behalf of women, the more
challenges it poses for them. From the point of contact with a frontline police
officer, to presenting evidence at court, to dispositions by the
court—whether criminal or civil—all present a range
of hurdles for
women to negotiate. The nature of these experiences can be contingent on a wide
range of variables, including class,
ethnicity and cultural
background.
However, a
major contributing factor is fear: fear of their partner, fear of the system and
fear of what they might lose by exposing
themselves to the criminal justice
process (e.g., their role as mothers to their children). These concerns have
persisted, decades
of policy activity notwithstanding. Responding to these
concerns is not solely about training (criminal justice) professionals to
respond more appropriately to women living with violence, though without a
doubt, more could be done in this respect.
In
particular, the creation of a new offence does not deal with any of the
well-documented concerns women have for not engaging with
the criminal justice
process and, as Douglas (2018) has observed, may also create new opportunities
for what she has termed ‘legal
systems abuse’: perpetrators using
the legal system to further assert control over their partners (see, e.g.,
research on protection
orders and the criminalisation of women victims: Douglas
and Fitzgerald 2018; Douglas and Nancarrow 2014). Additionally, such abuse
can
also contribute to the criminalisation of women, adding to their concerns about
engagement with legal processes at all (see further
Tolmie
2018).
The concerns
consistently expressed by women also touch upon questions of what it is they
would want from any intervention, legal
or otherwise (as opposed to what
activists might want or what policymakers and practitioners might be charged
with delivering). Classic
understandings of women living with violence point to
evidence that, if it is the woman herself who has asked for help or support,
more often than not she just wants the behaviour of her partner, both violent
and non-violent in all of its intimidating and fear-inducing
manifestations, to
stop (see, inter alia, Kirkwood 1993). Sometimes, for some women, love still
matters (Kuennen 2014). So, wanting
undesirable behaviour to stop does not
necessarily equate with wanting a partner’s behaviour to be subjected to
criminal sanction.
Clearly,
for some behaviours, particularly those of physical violence, a woman’s
wishes in this respect can quite legitimately,
in terms of the law, be ignored.
Even in cases where women do seek legal intervention and a punitive criminal
justice system outcome,
the criminalisation of coercive control in and of itself
does little to address the long-held barriers women victims of IPV have
faced in
accessing justice (on this, see further Walklate, Fitz-Gibbon and McCulloch
2018). To this end, introducing coercive control
as a standalone offence
presumes that women will have access to police, that police will have access to
the required evidence, and
the legal frameworks of the inherently masculine
criminal court system will be open to their experiences of a pattern of abuse.
When
considered from that vantage, it is a lot to expect from a single piece of
legislative law
reform.
Consequently, when
women’s everyday experiences of control in their relationships (not all of
which will be seen by them as
coercive) are put alongside what they might want
from any intervention, there is no necessary neatness of fit. Indeed, neither is
there a neatness of fit with the policy responses claiming to meet their
interests. Two issues arise as a consequence of this. The
first is concerned
with the relationship between individual autonomy and agency and the ongoing
concern to criminalise coercive control.
The second is concerned with how
coercive control in and of itself can downplay violence in relationships, which
arguably, is the
very issue that is better dealt with through a legal response.
Each of these will be discussed in
turn.
Kuennen (2014)
discusses coercive control and the efforts to embrace this concept in criminal
justice as the legal erasure of agency.
This observation is similar to that made
by Brunk (1979) some time ago in his discussion of the legal dilemma posed by
the concept
of coercion per se and what this implies for individual
choice—or, as Kuennen (2014) might say—agency. Perhaps, to put
it
more squarely in the discussion here, the question arises as to what this legal
erasure implies for women who choose to live with
constraint, whether that be
through commitment (Crossman and Hardesty 2018) or as a result of any other
motivation. There is here
a further question concerning what a normal
relationship might look like and who decides on such
normality.
The criminal law
proves a blunt instrument for drawing such distinctions; as Hanna (2009: 1468)
has argued, it ‘forces the question
of coercion into a yes or no answer.
The line between free choice and coercion gets drawn somewhere—and you are
either coercive
or not’ (see also Walklate, Fitz-Gibbon and McCulloch
2018). Problematically, when these distinctions are drawn in the realm
of law,
it is not the individual experiencing the behaviour who decides whether the
actions constitute coercive control or which
actions should be considered
criminal, but rather the legal actors involved. The erasure of agency in this
way carries implications,
of course, not just for women in cases of coercive
control, but for all women, particularly as legal discourses can be, and are,
used for purposes other than they were intended (Smart 1989). The potential
slippage from individual women to all women highlights
the slipperiness of
coercive control as a concept (Hamberger, Larsen and Lehrner 2017), and as a
result, its lack of specificity—particularly
in the law—carries with
it significant unintended consequences for its
use.
Ultimately, of course,
the law itself must also be recognised as a site of coercion, alongside a range
of other sources of sanction
that coerce individuals to do things because they
are afraid or intimidated to do otherwise. Brauer, Tittle and Antonaccio (2017)
make the distinction between erratic and oppressive coercion in endeavouring to
understand coercion as a feature of all aspects of
offending behaviour and its
consequences. However, for the purposes of this discussion, it is sufficient to
note that the proponents
of coercive control view its presence in women’s
lives as though it was separate and separable from their experiences of coercion
in other aspects of their lives and/or separate from the human condition
experienced by
everyone.
The second issue
to be addressed here, the erasure of physical violence, has been discussed at
length by Walby and Towers (2018).
Their concern with downplaying physical
violence and its importance in intimate partner relationships is as much
methodological as
it is conceptual, although these two concerns are connected.
The absence of conceptual clarity impedes measurement efforts, and for
Walby and
Towers (2018), any agenda focused on violence against women demands accurate
measures, since it is these measurements and
the counting of violence that
ultimately persuade governments to take action across a wide range of domains,
including but not limited
to the legal
domain.
However, police
preoccupation with the presence of physical violence, for example, as a means of
informing their decision-making in
relation to violence against women is well
documented (see, e.g., Robinson, Pinchevsky and Guthrie, 2018). Physical
violence can
more often than not be evidenced and can result in the kind of
criminalisation that is pursued by those wanting to criminalise coercive
control. Thus, there is a conundrum here in the way in which coercive control as
a concept downplays the physically violent aspect
of women’s lives that
can be responded to more or less adequately by the incident-led response of the
law, while it simultaneously
places demands on criminal justice systems that, as
yet, have been shown to be less well equipped to respond to when compared with
response to physical
violence.
In this respect,
a concern emerges that begs the question of whether, in seeking to criminalise a
wider range of abusive behaviours,
the day-to-day operation of an offence of
coercive control may also serve to hide acts of physical violence. Such hiding
has far-reaching
implications in terms of assessments of perpetrator risk,
management of victim safety and seriousness of criminal justice system
intervention.
Conclusion: Coercive control, meaning and
consequences
A number of themes run through this paper, some of
which contribute to a bigger question and debate recently posed by Goodmark
(2018)
on decriminalising domestic violence. The coercive control creep
documented here stands as testimony to some aspects of that more
significant
question. In particular, the criminalisation of coercive control may fail women
in two respects. Firstly, it arguably
fails at the conceptual level, in
misunderstanding the coercive nature of the law and the inability to appreciate
how this concept
contributes to the process of erasing women’s agency.
Secondly, it fails at the experiential level, in failing to see women’s
lives as a whole, particularly their reluctances to engage with criminal
justice. Put simply, coercive control fails to ‘see’
responses to
violence against women holistically and, in so doing, leaves the subject of law
untouched (Naffine 2003).
Some time ago, Naffine
(1990) observed that the subject of law was the rational, middle-class
entrepreneurial male. Law was made and
practised with this subject in mind. This
subject renders all those who fall outside of its parameters
‘other’, in both
their experiences of the law and the likelihood
that the law can ‘see’ or ‘hear’ them (Easteal, Bartels
and
Mittal 2019; Hudson 2006). In her later essay, Naffine (2003) sees little to
be optimistic about the hold this subject of law has
on law’s formulation
and practice. However, following Smart (1989) and more recently, Howe and
Alaattinoğlu (2019), this
does not necessarily mean that law is not a site
for action. It is. However, the law itself will never be enough, and this truism
has abounded in this field since the advent of second-wave feminism (see, e.g.,
Wilson 1983). Coercive control is a constituent element
in framing our
understandings of the pervasive impact of a wide range of behaviours on
women’s lives, but the law and its inherent
power structure is a very
blunt instrument to address the concerns it brings to the fore. In this respect,
more law is definitely
not the answer and only furthers the exclusion of those
already excluded from criminal justice.
Correspondence:
Sandra Walklate, Eleanor Rathbone Chair of
Sociology at the University of Liverpool (Liverpool, United Kingdom) conjoint
Chair of
Criminology, Monash University (Victoria, Australia). Email: S.L.Walklate@liverpool.ac.uk
Dr Kate Fitz-Gibbon, School of Social Sciences,
Faculty of Arts, Monash University. 20 Chancellor's Walk, Clayton VIC 3800,
Australia. Email: kate.fitzgibbon@monash.edu
References
Blagg H (2016) Crime, Aboriginality and the Decolonisation of Justice.
2nd edn. Sydney: Federation Press.
Bishop C (2016) Why it’s so hard to prosecute cases of coercive or
controlling behaviour. The Conversation, 31 October. Available at https://theconversation.com/why-its-so-hard-to-prosecute-cases-of-coercive-or-controlling-behaviour-66108
(accessed 11 September 2019)
Bishop C and Bettinson V (2018) Evidencing domestic violence, including
behaviour that falls under the new offence of ‘controlling
or coercive
behaviour’. The International Journal of Evidence & Proof
22(1): 3–29. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1365712717725535
Brauer JR, Tittle C and Antonaccio O (2017) The costs of coercive control:
Assessing behavioral and mental health correlates of erratic
and oppressive
coercion. Justice Quarterly 36(2): 255–286. https://doi.org/10.1080/07418825.2017.1403643
Brennan IR, Burton V, Gormally S and O’Leary N (2018) Service provider
difficulties in operationalizing coercive control. Violence Against Women
25(6): 635–653. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1077801218797478
Brunk GG (1979) The problem of voluntariness and coercion in the negotiated
plea. Law and Society Review 13(2): 527–553. DOI:
10.2307/3053267.
Burman M and Brooks-Hay O (2018) Aligning policy and law? The creation of a
domestic abuse offence incorporating coercive control.
Criminology &
Criminal Justice 18(1): 67–83. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1748895817752223
Callaghan JEM, Alexander JH, Sixsmith J and Fellin LC (2018) Beyond
“witnessing”: Children’s experiences of coercive
control in
domestic violence and abuse. Journal of Interpersonal Violence 33(10):
1551–1581. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0886260515618946
Chung D (2005) Violence, control, romance and gender equality: Young women
and heterosexual relationships. Women’s Studies International Forum
28(6): 445–455. https://psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1016/j.wsif.2005.09.005
Crossman K and Hardesty J (2018) Placing coercive control at the center: What
are the processes of coercive control and what makes
control coercive?
Psychology of Violence 8(2): 196–206. https://psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1037/vio0000094
Crossman KA, Hardesty JL and Raffaelli M (2016) “He could scare me
without laying a hand on me”: Mothers’ experiences
of nonviolent
coercive control during marriage and after separation. Violence Against
Women 22(4): 454–473. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1077801215604744
Curtis J (2019) Woman, 65, who killed her husband with a hammer after decades
of abuse weeps in court as she has her 2011 murder conviction
overturned in
watershed moment for ‘coercive control’ law. Daily Mail, 1
March. Available at https://www.dailymail.co.uk/news/article-6756499/Wife-65-killed-husband-hammer-freed.html
(accessed 1 March 2019)
Douglas H (2015) Do we need a specific domestic violence offence?
Melbourne University Law Review 39(2): 434–471.
Douglas H (2018) Legal systems abuse and coercive control. Criminology
& Criminal Justice 18(1): 84–99. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1748895817728380
Douglas H and Fitzgerald R (2018) The domestic violence protection order
system as entry to the criminal justice system for Aboriginal
and Torres Strait
Islander people. International Journal for Crime, Justice and Social
Democracy 7(3): 41–57. https://doi.org/10.5204/ijcjsd.v7i3.499
Douglas H, Harris BA and Dragiewicz M (2019) Technology-facilitated domestic
and family violence: Women’s experiences. British Journal of
Criminology 59(3): 551–570. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjc/azy068
Douglas H and Nancarrow H (2014) Perils of using law: A critique of
protection orders to respond to intimate partner violence. In
Johnson H, Fisher
BS and Jaquier V (eds) Critical Issues on Violence against Women:
International Perspectives and Promising Strategies: 77–90. London:
Routledge.
Easteal P, Bartels L and Mittal R (2019) The importance of understanding the
victims’ ‘reality’ of domestic violence.
Alternative Law
Journal 44(1): 11–16. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1037969X18790040
Elizabeth V (2017) Custody stalking: A mechanism of coercively controlling
mothers following separation. Feminist Legal Studies 25(2):
185–201. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10691-017-9349-9
Fitz-Gibbon K (2014) Homicide Law Reform, Gender and the Provocation
Defence: A Comparative Perspective. London: Palgrave-MacMillan.
Fitz-Gibbon K, McCulloch J and Walklate S (2017) Australia should be cautious
about introducing laws on coercive control to stem domestic
violence. The
Conversation, 27 November. Available at https://theconversation.com/australia-should-be-cautious-about-introducing-laws-on-coercive-control-to-stem-domestic-violence-87579
(accessed 11 September 2019).
Fitz-Gibbon K, Maher JMM, McCulloch J and Walklate S (2018) Victorian
government should be wary of introducing a stand-alone offence
of non-fatal
strangulation. The Conversation, 3 August. Available at https://theconversation.com/victorian-government-should-be-wary-of-introducing-a-stand-alone-offence-of-non-fatal-strangulation-100517
(accessed 11 September 2019).
Gill AK and Harrison K (2016) Police responses to intimate partner sexual
violence in South Asian communities. Policing 10(4): 446–455. https://doi.org/10.1093/police/paw027
Goodmark L (2015) Exporting without license: The American attempt to end
intimate partner abuse worldwide. In Goel R and Goodmark
L (eds) Comparative
Perspectives on Gender Violence: Lessons from Efforts Worldwide: 3–14.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Goodmark L (2017) Should domestic violence be decriminalized? Harvard
Journal of Law and Gender 40: 54–113.
Goodmark L (2018) Decriminalizing Domestic Violence: A Balanced Policy
Approach to Intimate Partner Violence. California: University of California
Press.
Gotsis T (2018) NSW’s strangulation offence: Time for further reform?
NSW Parliamentary Research Service Issues Backgrounder, Number 3. Sydney:
Parliamentary Library.
Hamberger K, Larsen SE and Lehrner A (2017) Coercive control in intimate
partner violence. Aggression and Violent
Behavior 37: 1–11. https://psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1016/j.avb.2017.08.003
Hanna C (2009) The paradox of progress: Translating Evan Stark’s
coercive control into legal doctrine for abused women. Violence against
Women 15(12): 1458–1476. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1077801209347091
Harris B and Woodlock D (2019) Digital coercive control: Insights from two
landmark domestic violence studies. The British Journal of Criminology
59(3): 530–550. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjc/azy052
Heward-Belle S (2017) Exploiting the ‘good mother’ as a tactic of
coercive control: Domestically violent men’s assaults
on women as mothers.
Journal of Women and Social Work 32(3): 374–389. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0886109917706935
Home Office (2015) Controlling or coercive behaviour in an intimate or family
relationship: Statutory guidance framework. London:
Home Office.
Howe A and Alaattinoğlu D (eds) (2019) Contesting Femicide Feminism
and the Power of Law Revisited. London: Routledge.
Hudson B (2006) Beyond white man’s justice: Race, gender and justice in
late modernity. Theoretical Criminology 10(1): 29–47. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1362480606059981
Johnson M (1995) Patriarchal terrorism and common couple violence: Two forms
of violence against women. Journal of Marriage and the Family 57(2):
283–294. https://psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.2307/353683
Kelly L and Westmarland N (2016) Naming and defining “domestic
violence” lessons from research with violent men. Feminist Review
112(1): 113–127. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/fr.2015.52
Kirkwood C (1993) Leaving Abusive Partners. London: Sage
Kuennen T (2014) Love matters. Arizona Law Review 56(4):
977–1015.
Law Commission (2016) Strangulation: The case for a new offence. Report
138. Wellington, New Zealand: Law Commission.
McClenaghan M and Boutaud C (2017) Questions raised over patchy take-up of
domestic violence law. The Bureau of Investigative Journalism, 24
November. Available at www.thebureauinvestigates.com/stories/2017-11-24/coercive-control-concerns
(accessed 11 September 2019).
McLeod D (2018) Coercive control: Impacts on children and young people in the
family environment. Devon, England: Research in Practice.
Available at https://www.basw.co.uk/resources/coercive-control-impacts-children-and-young-people-family-environment
(accessed 11 September 2019).
McMahon M and McGorrery P (2016) Criminalising emotional abuse, intimidation
and economic abuse in the context of family violence:
The Tasmanian experience.
University of Tasmania Law Review 35(2): 1–22.
Manjoo R (2016) Special guest contribution: Violence against women as a
barrier to the realisation of human rights and the effective
exercise of
citizenship. Feminist Review 112(1): 11–26. https://doi.org/10.1057%2Ffr.2015.54
Midson B (2016) Coercive control and criminal responsibility: Victims who
kill their abusers. Criminal Law Forum 27(4): 417–442. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10609-016-9292-5
Naffine N (1990) Law and the Sexes. London: Allen and Unwin.
Naffine N (2003) Who are law’s persons? From Cheshire cats to
responsible subjects. Modern Law Review 66(3): 346–367. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-2230.6603002
Office of National Statistics (2018) Domestic Abuse in England and Wales:
Year Ending March 2017. Available at https://www.ons.gov.uk/peoplepopulationandcommunity/crimeandjustice/bulletins/domesticabuseinenglandandwales/yearendingmarch2017
(accessed 11 September 2019).
Ortiz AM (2018) Invisible bars: Adapting the crime of false imprisonment to
better address coercive control and domestic violence
in Tennessee.
Vanderbilt Law Review 71: 682–715.
Pitman T (2017) Living with coercive control: Trapped within a complex web of
double standards, double binds and boundary violations.
British Journal of
Social Work 47(1): 143–161. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjsw/bcw002
Radford L and Hester M (2006) Mothering through Domestic Violence.
London: Jessica Kingsley.
Renzetti C (1992) Violent Betrayal: Partner Abuse in Lesbian
Relationships. Newbury Park, California: Sage.
Robinson AL, Myhill A and Wire J (2018) Practitioner (mis)understandings of
coercive control in England and Wales. Criminology and Criminal Justice
18(1): 29–49. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1748895817728381
Robinson, AL, Pinchevsky G and Guthrie J (2018) A small constellation: Risk
factors informing police perceptions of domestic abuse.
Policing and
Society 28 (2): 189-204. https://doi.org/10.1080/10439463.2016.1151881
Schechter S (1982) Women and Male Violence: The Visions and Struggles of
the Battered Women’s Movement. Cambridge, MA: South End Press.
Sheehy E (2018) Expert evidence on coercive control in support of
self-defence: The trial of Teresa Craig. Criminology & Criminal
Justice 18(1): 100–14. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1748895817733524
Smart C (1989) Feminism and the Power of Law. London: Routledge.
Stansfield R and Williams KR (2018) Coercive control between intimate
partners: An application to nonfatal strangulation. Journal of Interpersonal
Violence. Advance online publication. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F0886260518795175
Stark E (2007) Coercive Control: How Men Entrap Women in Personal
Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stark E and Hester M (2019) Coercive control: Update and review. Violence
against Women 25(1): 81–104. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1077801218816191
Thiara RK, Hague G and Mullender A (2011) Losing out on both counts: Disabled
women and domestic violence. Disability & Society 26(6):
757–771. https://doi.org/10.1080/09687599.2011.602867
Theakston S (2019) ‘Horrific act.’ Why Kentucky needs to make
non-fatal strangulation a felony. Lexington Herald Leader, 11 February.
Available at https://www.kentucky.com/opinion/op-ed/article226087915.html
(accessed 11 September 2019).
Tolmie J (2018) Coercive control: To criminalize or not to criminalize?
Criminology & Criminal Justice 18(1): 50–66. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1748895817746712
Tuerkheimer D (2007) Renewing the call to criminalize domestic violence: An
assessment three years later. George Washington Law Review 75:
101-114.
Walby S and Towers J (2018) Untangling the concept of coercive control:
Theorizing domestic violent crime. Criminology & Criminal Justice,
18(1): 7–28. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1748895817743541
Walklate S and Fitz-Gibbon K (2018) Criminology and the violence(s) of
Northern Theorizing: A critical examination of policy transfer
in relation to
violence against women from the global north to the global south. In Carrington
K, Hogg R, Scott J and Sozzo M (eds)
The Palgrave Handbook of Criminology and
the Global South: 847–865. Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan.
Walklate S, Fitz-Gibbon K and McCulloch J (2018) Is more law the answer?
Seeking justice for victims of intimate partner violence
through the reform of
legal categories. Criminology & Criminal Justice 18(1):
115–121. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1748895817728561
Wiener C (2017) Seeing what is ‘invisible in plain sight’:
Policing coercive control. The Howard Journal of Crime and Justice 56(4):
500–515. https://doi.org/10.1111/hojo.12227
Williamson E (2010) Living in the world of the domestic violence perpetrator:
Negotiating the unreality of coercive control. Violence Against Women
16(12): 1412–1423. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F1077801210389162
Wilson, E. (1983) What is to be done about violence against women?
Harmondsworth; Penguin
Women’s Aid (2019) Women’s Aid comments on Sally Challen’s
appeal verdict. Women’s Aid, 28 February. Available at https://www.womensaid.org.uk/womens-aid-comments-on-sally-challens-appeal-verdict/
(accessed 11 September 2019).
World Health Organization (2013) Global and Regional Estimates of Violence
Against Women: Prevalence and Health Effects of Intimate Partner Violence and
Non-Partner
Sexual Violence. Geneva: World Health Organization.
Legislation cited
Domestic Abuse (Scotland) Act 2018 (UK).
Domestic Violence Act (Ireland) 2018 (UK).
Family Violence Act 2004 (Tas).
Family Violence (Amendments) Act 2018 (NZ).
Serious Crime Act (England and Wales) 2015 (UK).
Cases cited
R v Wickham HC Auckland CRI-2009-090-010723 (20 December 2010).
R v Wihongi [2011] NZCA 592.
R v Wihongi [2011] NZCA 592; [2012] 1 NZLR 775.
[1] The two NZ cases analysed by
Midson (2016: 425–426) are R v Wickham HC Auckland CRI-2009-090-010723 (20
December 2010) and
R v Wihongi [2011] NZCA 592, [2012] 1 NZLR 775.
[2] However, the importance of the
presence of children is specifically mentioned in the Scottish legislation cited
above (see further,
Stark and Hester 2019).
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/IntJlCrimJustSocDem/2019/41.html