![]() |
Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
University of New South Wales Law Journal |
![]() |
[2] In the constitutional setting, a preamble can fulfil two important functions.[2] First, in its symbolic aspect, a preamble can capture and chart, in a pithy and quotable form, the history and aspirations of a nation. Although a preamble does not create substantive rights or obligations, its symbolic aspect may assist in the interpretation of the constitution itself by providing normative guidance. Thus, in its second, justiciable aspect, a preamble can be used in constitutional interpretation and in the construction of statutes and the development of the common law as a legally useful statement of fundamental values.
[3] The poignant and evocative Preamble to the recently proclaimed Constitution of the Republic of South Africa demonstrates the potential for constitutional preambles to serve as a means of healing past divisions and as instruments of reconciliation. That Preamble recognises the ‘injustices of our past’ and affirms a common belief ‘that South Africa belongs to all who live in it, united in our diversity’ and that the new Constitution was adopted to ‘establish a society based on democratic values, social justice and fundamental human rights’. Other preambles demonstrate a similar relationship to the social and political culture of a nation. In the Constitution of Ireland, the Preamble reads like a Papal decree, invoking ‘the name of the Most Holy Trinity, from Whom is all authority and to Whom, as our final end, all actions both of men and States must be referred’. This is consistent with the historical significance of Catholicism in the definition of Irish Republican identity. The Constitution of Japan and the German Constitution (the Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany) express the desire for ‘world peace’ in their respective Preambles. While some preambles serve as ‘manifestos of nationalism’, others, such as those of Germany and Japan, turn their backs on recent historical experience, acknowledging the past in the hope that things will be different in the future.[3]
[4] The historical traditions of Australian political culture, influenced heavily by those of Great Britain, tend to be sceptical of constitutional or political declarations of democratic values. We have no ‘Fourth of July’ nor ‘Independence Day’ to serve as our founding moment. The very concept of a preamble as a definitive statement of a people’s aspirations has its origins in the politics of the French and American revolutions in the late 18th century. Because Australia lacks a similar historical experience, such as the revolutionary overthrow of a monarchy or colonial overlord, we have not defined our national identity in a specific declaration of political principle.
[5] This paper examines the legal issues relating to the
current Preamble to the Australian Constitution
(‘Constitution’). After
tracing the origins of the current Preamble and examining its role and status
within the legal system, the paper proceeds
to discuss the emerging movement for
a new preamble. Finally, it examines whether a new preamble ought to be
justiciable, rather
than merely symbolic, and makes a case for justiciability.
The debate over and drafting of the preamble proposal put to the Australian
people in the referendum held on 6 November 1999 is the subject of
our companion article, ‘With Hope in God, the
Prime Minister and the Poet:
Lessons from the 1999 Referendum on the
Preamble’.[4]
Whereas the people of New South Wales, Victoria, South Australia, Queensland, and Tasmania, humbly relying on the blessing of Almighty God, have agreed to unite in one indissoluble Federal Commonwealth under the Crown of the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Ireland, and under the Constitution hereby established:
And whereas it is expedient to provide for the admission into the Commonwealth of other Australian Colonies and possessions of the Queen:
Be it therefore enacted by the Queen’s Most Excellent Majesty, by and with the advice and consent of the Lords Spiritual and Temporal, and Commons, in this present Parliament assembled, and by the authority of the same, as follows: –
[8] The founders
devoted little time to debating the Preamble in Adelaide in 1897 and Melbourne
in 1898 – with three exceptions.
First, concern over the word
‘Commonwealth’ stemmed from its alleged republican connotations.
Some delegates believed
that it evoked memories of the protectorate of Oliver
Cromwell.[10] Second, the
Preamble’s recitation of ‘one indissoluble Federal
Commonwealth’ arose in debates about whether a State
might be able to
secede from the new Federation.[11]
Third, delegates debated whether the Preamble should include God’s
blessing.[12] The inclusion of such
a phrase was due largely to the efforts of South Australian delegate Patrick
Glynn. In 1897 in Adelaide, Glynn
argued that the Preamble should include the
words ‘invoking Divine Providence’ to reflect the ‘great
central fact
of faith’ and the ‘spirit of reverence for the
Unseen’ that pervaded civil life in
Australia.[13] The Convention
rejected this by 17 votes to 11.[14]
After the Adelaide meeting, there was, according to Edmund Barton – later
Australia’s first Prime Minister and one of
the first members of the High
Court – ‘considerable argument and a certain degree of warmth about
this matter’.[15] Glynn then
made a second attempt in Melbourne in 1898, where he proposed the words
‘humbly relying upon the blessing of Almighty
God’.[16] This form of words
was accepted by the
Convention.[17]
have therefore to be regarded as promulgating principles, ideas or sentiments operating, at the time of the formation of the instrument, in the minds of the framers, and by them imparted to and approved by the people to whom it was submitted.[20]
[12] The framers, along with leading commentators of the time,
anticipated a role for the Preamble in constitutional interpretation.
This was a
factor in the inclusion of s 116 of the Constitution, which provides
that the Commonwealth cannot pass laws abrogating freedom of
religion.[21] Section 116 was
based upon a provision accepted at the 1891 Convention and drafted by Tasmanian
Attorney-General Andrew Inglis
Clark.[22]
In 1898, the section was retained in an amended form largely at the behest of
Henry Higgins, subsequently a justice of the High Court.
Higgins put the rather
far-fetched argument that the Commonwealth Parliament might be able to claim a
power to legislate in regard
to religion as a result of the Preamble’s
reference to ‘Almighty
God’.[23] According to
Higgins, s
116 was needed not to protect a fundamental human right, but
to
make it clear beyond doubt that the powers which the states individually have of making such laws as they like with regard to religion shall remain undisturbed and unbroken, and to make it clear that in framing this Constitution there is no intention whatever to give to the Federal Parliament the power to interfere in these matters.[24]
[14] Commentators writing on the newly enacted Constitution shared the
belief that the Preamble would be justiciable. Quick and Garran asserted that
sections of the Preamble:
may be of valuable service and potent effect in the Courts of the Commonwealth, aiding in the interpretation of words and phrases which may now appear comparatively clear, but which, in time to come, may be obscured by the raising of unexpected issues and by the conflict of newly emerging opinions.[27]
[16] Nevertheless, as George Winterton has suggested, the Preamble ‘will inevitably be employed in constitutional interpretation’,[30] although its persuasiveness will continue to be a matter of debate. According to Gregory Craven, the ordinary rules of statutory construction and analogous principles of constitutional interpretation suggest that the Preamble can be determinative of a legal question only where it assists in resolving existing ambiguity in the substantive provisions of the Constitution.[31] Craven is clearly correct. The Preamble should not be ascribed the same legal effect as an operative provision.
[17] Until recently, only two aspects of the Preamble seemed to invite judicial consideration as an aid to construing the Constitution’s operative provisions. One, the reference to ‘Almighty God’, was stripped of its potential interpretive significance by the inclusion of s 116. The other, the words ‘indissoluble Federal Commonwealth’, which Isaacs J described in Federated Saw Mill &c Employees of Australasia v James Moore & Son Proprietary Ltd (‘Woodworkers’ Case’)[32] as ‘pious aspirations for unity’, thus became the focus of what little judicial attention was paid to the Preamble. Outside of the courts, the phrase has been considered in debate over the potential for secession by one or more States.[33] Craven has argued that the phrase could not, by itself, provide a constitutional barrier to a State seceding, stating that the Preamble ‘could never operate as a direct prohibition of the unilateral secession of a State’.[34]
[18] In High
Court judgments, references to the phrase ‘indissoluble Federal
Commonwealth’ have generally had little legal
significance. Judges have
typically used this evocative phrase to describe the historical event of
Federation or to convey a sense
of the sentiment of the time, rather than as
support for a particular legal
conclusion.[35] However, there are
few cases in which the phrase has been cited in support of a legal conclusion.
In Victoria v Commonwealth (‘Payroll Tax
Case’),[36] Menzies J, in
articulating the rationale for an implied doctrine of State immunity from
Commonwealth laws, stated that a ‘constitution
providing for an
indissoluble Federal Commonwealth must protect both Commonwealth and
States’. In Queensland v Commonwealth (‘Second Territory
Senators Case’),[37]
Barwick CJ raised the indissoluble federal nature of the Commonwealth in
reasoning to the conclusion that Territory residents could
not elect
representatives to the Senate. On the other hand, Toohey J in Kruger v
Commonwealth (‘Stolen Generations
Case’)[38] referred to the
Preamble in support of his conclusion that the Territories form part of the
federal system – at least for the
purposes of Chapter III
‘federal’ judicial power. Finally, in R v Hughes, Kirby J
found that ‘[t]his Court should be the upholder, and not the destroyer, of
lawful cooperation between the organs of
government in all of the constituent
parts into which the Commonwealth of Australia is
divided’.[39] He went on to
argue:
No other approach is appropriate to the interpretation of the basic law of the ‘indissoluble Federal Commonwealth’ upon which the people of Australia agreed when the Constitution was adopted and which they are taken to accept for their governance today.[40]
[20] In R v
Sharkey,[41] Latham CJ revealed
a further, more imaginative, possibility for the Preamble that foreshadowed more
contemporary controversies. He
invoked the Preamble’s description of a
Commonwealth ‘under the Crown’ in deciding on the validity of a
Commonwealth
sedition law. The High Court was asked to rule on a provision of
the Crimes Act 1914 (Cth) that prohibited the publication of
anti-monarchy propaganda. In finding the provision constitutionally valid,
Latham CJ seemed
to suggest that the express incidental power, granted to the
Commonwealth in s
51(xxxix) of the Constitution, could operate
upon the Preamble with the effect that:
Laws which are directed to the protection and maintenance of the legal and political organization of the Commonwealth and of the Commonwealth in its legal and political relations may properly be enacted under [s 51(xxxix)].[42]
[22] The course of Australia’s more recent constitutional development has suggested new contexts in which the Preamble might have value as an interpretive tool. One of these new potential uses is that foreshadowed by Latham CJ: to assist in identifying the nature of Australia’s constitutional connection with the UK. That question arose in Sue v Hill[43] in 1999, exactly 50 years after the decision in R v Sharkey, and in very different social, political and legal circumstances. Heather Hill, a dual British-Australian citizen, asserted that she was not a ‘subject or citizen of a foreign power’ within the meaning of s 44(i) of the Constitution, and thus that she was not disqualified from holding a seat in the Senate. In arguing that the UK should not be regarded as a foreign power, Hill relied upon, among other things, the Preamble’s reference to the creation of the Commonwealth ‘under the Crown of the United Kingdom’. This, it was argued, demonstrated a special and immutable relationship between Australia and the UK. The leading judgment of Gleeson CJ, Gummow and Hayne JJ, however, denied that the terms of the Preamble have any significance for the legal relationship between Australia and the UK.[44] They looked instead to other evidence, such as the Australia Acts 1986 (Imp/Cth), to confirm that the UK should now be regarded as a foreign power.
[23] Justice Michael Kirby of the High Court, writing extra-judicially, has raised the question whether the Preamble’s reference to the creation of ‘one indissoluble Federal Commonwealth under the Crown’ would prevent Australia from becoming a republic or require steps to be taken other than a successful referendum under s 128 of the Constitution.[45] It might be argued that the Preamble creates an unbreakable link between our system of government and the Crown that could not be severed even by a referendum. However, this argument is untenable. As a mere statement of intent, the Preamble could not realistically be given an operation that would supersede that of the substantive provisions of the Constitution, as amended. Moreover, such an interpretation would run counter to the emerging notion that the efficacy of the Constitution now rests upon the sovereignty of the Australian people, and not upon its enactment by the UK Parliament. If the Preamble was not itself amended as part of the referendum that transformed Australia into a republic, and the words ‘under the Crown’ were retained, this would produce an anachronism rather than a constitutional contradiction of legal significance.
[24] According to Mason CJ in Australian Capital Television Pty Ltd v Commonwealth (‘Australian Capital Television’),[46] the passage of the Australia Acts 1986 (Imp/Cth) ‘marked the end of the legal sovereignty of the Imperial Parliament and recognised that ultimate sovereignty resided in the Australian people’. After the severing of legal ties with the UK, a new rationale was needed to explain why the Constitution is binding. It might be thought that the Preamble supports the contemporary notion of ‘popular sovereignty’[47] – that is, the idea that the present legitimacy of the Constitution ‘lies exclusively in the original adoption (by referenda) and subsequent maintenance (by acquiescence) of its provisions by the people’.[48] However, no judgment of the High Court has yet referred to the Preamble, which begins ‘Whereas the people’, as evidence of popular sovereignty. By contrast, in Australian Capital Television, Dawson J pointed to the terms of the Preamble as a consideration militating against the notion of popular sovereignty. According to Dawson J, not only does the Preamble serve as an ongoing reminder of the Constitution’s origins in an Act of the British Parliament, it also represents a conscious departure from the United States model of preambular confirmation of popular sovereignty.[49]
[25] The realm of implied rights is another contemporary context in which the Preamble might have taken on some significance as an interpretive tool. Yet, with the exception of one isolated and since disavowed instance, judges have been reluctant to underpin their recognition of new implied rights with references to the Preamble. The first invocation of the Preamble in the context of implied rights appeared in Justice Gaudron’s judgment in Australian Capital Television. In that case, the Court held that the Constitution contains an implied freedom of political communication. Gaudron J took account of the Preamble’s reference to the fact that ‘the people ... have agreed to unite’ in the new Federal Commonwealth, finding that this ‘reinforced’ her conclusion, drawn principally from other provisions of the Constitution, that ‘[r]epresentative parliamentary democracy is a fundamental part of the Constitution’.[50]
[26] While the Preamble represented only a secondary consideration for Gaudron J in Australian Capital Television, it took on greater significance for other members of the Court in Leeth v Commonwealth (‘Leeth’).[51] The plaintiff in Leeth, a ‘federal offender’ serving a sentence in a State gaol, contested the validity of the Commonwealth Prisoners Act 1967 (Cth). At the time of Leeth’s sentencing, s 4 of that Act instructed judges sentencing ‘federal offenders’ to set a minimum non-parole period by reference to the criteria set out in the legislation of each State. This ensured uniform parole expectations for all prisoners – State and federal – within a single State prison. However, it meant that parole expectations would differ among prisoners convicted of the same Commonwealth offence, depending upon the State in which sentencing took place. This result, the plaintiff argued, infringed an implied principle of equality found in the Constitution.
[27] Three
members of the High Court referred to the Preamble in the course of their
reasoning. Justice Brennan commented that, if
the law being challenged had
allowed different maximum penalties (as opposed to different non-parole periods)
to be prescribed for
the same offence, then the plaintiff’s arguments
would have had ‘much
force’.[52] According to
Brennan J,
[i]t would be offensive to the constitutional unity of the Australian people ‘in one indissoluble Federal Commonwealth’ recited in the first preamble to the Commonwealth of Australia Constitution Act 1900, to expose offenders against the same law of the Commonwealth to different maximum penalties dependent on the locality of the court by which the offender is convicted and sentenced.[53]
As the preamble ... make[s] plain, that conceptual basis was the free agreement of ‘the people’ – all the people – of the federating Colonies to unite in the Commonwealth under the Constitution. Implicit in that free agreement was the notion of the inherent equality of the people.[54]
[30] The suggestion that the Constitution contains an implied principle of legal equality, operating as a limitation on governmental power, was disavowed in the Stolen Generations Case. The approach of Deane and Toohey JJ in Leeth was rejected by a High Court majority composed of Dawson, Gaudron, McHugh and Gummow JJ. Justice Dawson, with whom McHugh J agreed, argued that it is illegitimate to invoke the ‘conceptual basis’ of the Constitution to derive limitations on express grants of power. The majority agreed that, to the extent that the Constitution does protect legal equality, that protection arises exclusively from the Chapter III grant of federal judicial power. As a consequence, while the reasoning in Leeth indicates the possibilities presented by the Preamble, they are not likely to find favour with the current High Court.
[31] Precisely why the High Court has been, and remains, disinclined to use the Preamble in constitutional interpretation is unclear. At least two factors appear to have contributed. First, it ought not be overlooked that the Preamble offers rather slim pickings for judges seeking interpretive assistance. By today’s standards the Preamble is a bland, largely inconsequential collection of sentiments that could have only a limited and sporadic relevance to the array of constitutional problems currently facing the Court. While such sentiments can still assist in a very limited way in understanding what lay in the minds of the drafters of the Constitution, they are arguably now only of historical interest.
[32] Secondly, the placement of
the Preamble – that is, its position outside the operative provisions of
the Constitution
– renders it a dubious source of guidance, at least where assistance might
be found within the text or structure of the Constitution itself. The
Preamble’s location is likely to have played a role in its relegation to a
position of secondary importance. The
High Court has generally been cautious in
seeking interpretive guidance from extrinsic material, that is, from sources
beyond the
‘four corners’ of the Constitution. In a related
area, the High Court has been similarly reluctant to use of the Debates of the
1890s Conventions that drafted the Constitution. From the time
of the Engineers Case in 1920, the Court rejected use of the Debates in
the interpretation of the Constitution. The Court only revised its approach and
permitted reference to the Convention Debates on a limited basis in 1988 in its
unanimous
decision in Cole v
Whitfield.[55] The Court has yet
to set out any like statement of approach to the Preamble.
[35] In 1993, the report of the Republic Advisory Committee found that the issue of a new preamble was ‘“relevant to the overall objective” of achieving a viable federal republic of Australia’,[58] and set out the options for change. The 1994 inquiries by the Civics Expert Group and the Centenary of Federation Advisory Committee attracted submissions that pointed to the need for a ‘restatement’ of the values of Australian citizenship and the constitutional recognition of Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander peoples. Throughout the 1990s, similar prominence was given to the importance of a new preamble in the policy documents of the Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Commission (‘ATSIC’), the Council for Aboriginal Reconciliation, the National Multicultural Advisory Council and the published material and public activities of the Constitutional Centenary Foundation. In addition, the growing activism of Australian women in the republic debate, which culminated in the Women’s Constitutional Convention, held in Canberra in January 1998,[59] also resulted in demands for a more inclusive preamble to the Constitution.[60]
[36] After the High Court’s decision in 1992 in Mabo v Queensland [No 2] (‘Mabo’),[61] discussion of a new preamble also came to concern the form of words that might be used to recognise Indigenous Australians in the Constitution.[62] The discriminatory treatment of Australia’s Indigenous peoples under the Constitution as enacted in 1901,[63] and the silence in the Constitution on their status and history since the 1967 referendum, arguably makes their inclusion in a new preamble an important part of any reconciliation process. [64]
[37] However,
support for a new preamble was not forthcoming from the Keating Government or
the Australian Republican Movement. Their
plans for constitutional change
centred upon a ‘minimalist’
republic.[65] Both were unwilling to
include a preamble as a key element in the achievement of a republic, believing
that a broader republican
platform would attract more opposition and thereby
bring about the defeat of any referendum.
[39] The frequently suggested alternative to a justiciable preamble is a preamble having only ‘symbolic’ value – a kind of meaning inaccessible to the courts in their development and interpretation of the law. Two methods have been put forward for creating such a preamble. First, its terms could be deliberately framed so as to minimise opportunities for judicial reliance. For instance, the Constitutional Centenary Foundation suggested in 1993 that a new preamble’s legal effect could be minimised by expressing particular values in the form of ‘ideas’ that motivate people, rather than as principles that underpin the Constitution.[67] Alternatively, a new preamble could be made subject to an express indication, either in the preamble itself or elsewhere in the Constitution, that courts are not to use the new preamble as an aid to interpreting the Constitution’s operative provisions.
[40] An argument raised in favour of making a new preamble justiciable relates to the role of the Australian people in the constitutional system. The contemporary High Court appears firmly committed to the principle of popular sovereignty.[68] This notion lends weight to the suggestion that judges ought not to be denied access to a statement of the shared values and aspirations of the Australian people, contained in a new preamble, in their interpretation of the Constitution.
[41] This
argument is strengthened when it is recognised that High Court judges will
inevitably distil and rely upon values, whether
they be their own or those of
Australian society, in the course of deciding cases and developing the
law.[69] Some members of the Court
have engaged overtly in this kind of process. For example, Gaudron J in
Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v
Teoh[70] relied upon
‘community values’ as a tool to assist in determining the legal
effect within Australia of a ratified international
convention. Sir Anthony
Mason has also argued that judges may have ‘reference to values which they
perceive to be desirable,
accepted community
values’.[71] He has
stated:
[I]t is impossible to interpret any instrument, let alone a constitution, divorced from values. To the extent they are taken into account, they should be acknowledged and should be accepted community values rather than mere personal values. The ever-present danger is that ‘strict and complete legalism’ will be a cloak for undisclosed and unidentified policy values.[72]
[43] The other key argument raised in favour of making any new preamble justiciable represents an objection to the possible adverse consequences of seeking to deny that justiciability. An express denial of a preamble’s legal significance may dull the symbolic impact of its contents and render the sentiments expressed within ‘hollow and hypocritical’.[74] Commentators have pointed out that fundamental values, of the kind typically recited in constitutional preambles, are significant precisely because they mark out the parameters of politico-legal legitimacy – the limits within which law-makers may act.[75] To assert those values, whilst simultaneously denying that they have any legal significance, appears at best a confusing contradiction and at worst an undermining of those values.[76]
[44] On the other hand, the legal arguments made for denying a new preamble a role in legal interpretation seem rooted in a concern about the way in which courts – and especially the High Court – might apply a new preamble. It is true that the drafters of a preamble could not foresee all the contexts in which courts might rely upon the values and other principles expressed,[77] and the most strenuous objections to the High Court’s reliance upon a new preamble have come from those determined to guard the Constitution against the implication of human rights principles. Some assert that the Constitution does not need reform in the area of rights protection, while others allude to the deliberate exclusion by the Constitution’s framers of provisions that might have had the effect of protecting individual rights.[78] For those sharing this outlook, the potential for a new constitutional preamble, reciting core values and principles, to establish a Bill of Rights ‘by the back door’ is reason enough to insist that it should be non-justiciable.[79] This reaction against justiciability was also a response to perceptions that, under Sir Anthony Mason and Sir Gerard Brennan, the High Court of the 1990s had become unduly ‘activist’. Decisions such as Mabo, Australian Capital Television and Wik Peoples v Queensland[80] led to arguments that nothing should be done that might give members of the Court any increased capacity to imply new rights or, in the field of native title law, discover new or expanded legal entitlements to land.
[45] Some of the proponents of a
non-justiciable preamble have turned to other jurisdictions in search of
examples to illustrate or
vindicate their concerns. In Re Resolution to Amend
the Constitution,[81]
the Supreme Court of Canada held that the Preamble to the Constitution Act
1867 (Imp) ‘has no enacting force’ and thus is not a source
of law. However, in the subsequent case of Re Provincial Court
Judges,[82] Lamer CJ, writing
for the majority, held that
the preamble does have important legal effects ... the preamble articulates ‘the political theory which the Act embodies’ ... It recognizes and affirms the basic principles which are the very source of the substantive provisions of the Constitution Act, 1867. As I have said above, those provisions merely elaborate those organizing principles in the institutional apparatus they create or contemplate. As such, the preamble is not only a key to construing the express provisions of the Constitution Act, 1867, but also invites the use of those organizing principles to fill out gaps in the express terms of the constitutional scheme. It is the means by which the underlying logic of the Act can be given the force of law.[83]
[47] In any event, Justices of the High Court, most notably Murphy J,[85] have proved capable of deriving a wide range of rights implications without recourse to the Preamble. For Murphy J and other judges willing to reason from the ‘silent constitutional principles ... not mentioned in the Constitution’[86] or ‘the democratic theme of the Constitution’,[87] the presence or absence of a justiciable preamble is unlikely to make much difference. Justice Murphy even implied rights from his conception of ‘the nature of our Constitution. It is a Constitution for a free society’.[88] Similarly, for a judge unwilling to reason from such sources, the presence of a justiciable preamble is equally unlikely to lead to the implication of new rights given the likelihood that the judge will feel constrained by the ordinary rules of statutory construction and the traditional principles of constitutional interpretation. Hence, it is difficult to see how a justiciable preamble would make any significant difference to the judicial propensity to derive implied rights.
[48] The Constitutional Commission suggested in 1988 that if the High Court had access to an expansively worded new preamble, this would not change the way in which the Court undertakes the process of constitutional interpretation, as it would add nothing to existing interpretive principles. In particular, the Commission referred to the approach to constitutional interpretation adopted by O’Connor J in Jumbunna Coal Mine NL v Victorian Coal Miners’ Association,[89] under which the Court should ‘always lean to the broader interpretation unless there is something in the context or in the rest of the Constitution to indicate that the narrower interpretation will best carry out its object and purpose’. The Commission found that ‘an expansively worded preamble [would not] seem to add anything where the Court approaches the Constitution in this way’.[90]
[49] This, on the other hand, may underestimate the impact of a justiciable preamble. The Commission’s conclusion does not account for situations in which the ‘broad interpretation’ of a provision will produce a construction that is inconsistent with fundamental rights. An example might be s 51(xxvi) of the Constitution, which gives the Commonwealth Parliament power to ‘make special laws for the people of any race’. The High Court has yet to determine whether this provision allows the Parliament to make only laws of ‘benefit’ to a particular race or whether it also permits laws that produce a detriment.[91] The Jumbunna principle of ‘broad interpretation’ would favour the latter result. However, if the Court had access to a new preamble declaring equality to be a shared value – or perhaps recounting the dispossession of Indigenous peoples in Australia – it may find support for the alternative, narrower, interpretation. In this context, at least, recourse to a new preamble could add to the High Court’s interpretive armoury.
[50] After assessing the arguments, we conclude that a new preamble to the Constitution should be justiciable. The legal ‘dangers’ posed by a new preamble are small and often overstated. To date, minimal use has been made of the current Preamble by Australian judges. It has been used sparingly to support conclusions grounded in other considerations, and has never been determinative of the outcome in a case. Even in Leeth, it is difficult to see that the Preamble actually made any difference to the result. Justices Deane and Toohey would have found an implied guarantee of equality under the law even if they had not had access to the Preamble.[92]
[51] Even if a new preamble were drafted to include contemporary values and aspirations, and placed at the front of the Constitution itself, it could not give rise to substantive rights, having no textual foundation in the Constitution, the decision of the Canadian Supreme Court in the Re Provincial Court Judges notwithstanding. A Court could not apply a preamble in this way without compromising its institutional legitimacy (and if a judge is prepared to suffer such a consequence they will not need to refer to a preamble anyway). It seems highly unlikely that a justiciable preamble could itself bring about the implication of new rights.
[52] The legal dangers of a justiciable preamble
are not only greatly over-emphasised; the whole notion of a non-justiciable
preamble
is also misconceived. It would demean the values set out in the
preamble. In addition, where a judge has reference to their understanding
of the
shared values of the Australian people in cases of ambiguity, it would be better
for the judge to refer to such values in
a preamble, formed through a process of
democratic deliberation, rather than to their own perceptions of such values. It
makes no
sense to deny judges access to a set of values endorsed by the people
and to force them instead to rely upon their own sense of such
values (which may
match those in the preamble in any
event).[93] Once it is recognised
that some use of values by judges is inevitable, they should not be denied
access to a set of values endorsed
by the community.
[54] Suggestions for the addition of a new preamble to the Constitution, to be placed
within that document at the head of its operative provisions, have generally
focused on the symbolic benefit that such
an addition may bring. Whether and to
what extent a new preamble should be ‘justiciable’ (ie, give rise to
legal consequences,
be they direct or indirect), has been a matter of
contention. As we see it, the risks presented by a justiciable preamble are
small,
particularly when weighed against the advantages of providing a symbolic
underpinning for the High Court’s development of the
concept of popular
sovereignty. Moreover, a legally sterile preamble would not retain the symbolic
potency intended for it.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/UNSWLawJl/2001/28.html